<h2>Introduction</h2> <p><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">There is a gap between being able to manipulate and read a language and being able to understand it. Particularly in the case of human-machine interaction because neither of them speaks the same language. This difference of nature between humans&rsquo; and machines&rsquo; ability to express thought has been at the foundation of the field of artificial intelligence (AI) since <span style="color:black">(A. Turing, 1950) </span>asked in his test if a machine, by playing a language game with humans, will be abl<span style="color:black">e to think by itself or to </span>&ldquo;carry out something which ought to be described as thinking but which is very different from what a man does&rdquo;.</span></span></span> <span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">This question received a famous negative answer with the thought experiment of the &ldquo;Chinese room&rdquo; of (J. Searle, 1980) where he states that a machine does not &ldquo;think&rdquo; by itself or &ldquo;understand&rdquo; propositions but only computes logical signs together and that therefore has no intelligence at all. This thought experiment led Searle to distinguish between weak and strong AI: weak AI being the typical kind of system we interact with every day and which is limited to performing specific tasks without any kind of self-awareness, and strong AI being the hypothetical model conscious of itself and able to understand multi-contextual situations as humans do.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Thus, from the beginning of AI&rsquo;s history, the question of meaning has taken a significant place. But moving from a theoretical question in the philosophy of the mind, computational linguistics took the problem of human-computer interaction from a practical aspect. Notably, the</span></span></span> <span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">question of meaning in AI has been reformulated as the &ldquo;symbol grounding problem&rdquo; by (S. Harnad, 1990) where, more precisely, Harnad asks how the semantic meaning of a sign and a proposition could be interpreted by a formal system:</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <blockquote> <p class="MsoQuote" style="margin: 13px 58px 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span style="color:#404040"><span style="font-style:italic"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="font-style:normal">&ldquo;How can the semantic interpretation of a formal symbol system be made&nbsp;</span></span><em><span lang="EN-US" style="color:#2e2e2e"><span style="font-style:normal">intrinsic</span></span></em><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="font-style:normal">&nbsp;to the system, rather than just parasitic on the meanings in our heads? How can the meanings of the meaningless symbol tokens, manipulated solely on the basis of their (arbitrary) shapes, be grounded in anything but other meaningless symbols?&rdquo;</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> </blockquote> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">In other words, h</span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">ow can we fill logical signs with semantic meaning for a machine? Is it possible to inscribe intentional content into data? If machines are mainly syntaxial systems able to analyze with precision logical structures, is there any way that the grammatical structure of a sentence or any proposition read by a machine could capture or at least reflect its meaning? This situation calls into question the problem of interpretation which is also the domain of hermeneutics. Here, we can draw historical lines to understand its link with AI.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px">&nbsp;</p> <h2>A Brief History of Hermeneutics: From Philology to Computers Analysis</h2> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Traditionally, hermeneutics is the science of the interpretation of symbols and sacred texts and </span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">its purpose is to reveal an esoteric or hidden meaning of the text with a high degree of symbolic interpretation that is supposed to be related to a particular level of reality by </span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">using different technic of interpretation (numerology, analogy, etc.). In </span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">philosophy, a science of interpretation can be originally located in the <i>On Interpretation</i> of Aristotle, which is a treatise on how ontology and language can be defined by logical and linguistic categories.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">It&nbsp;</span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">was between the 18<sup>th</sup> and 19<sup>th</sup> centuries with Friedrich Schleiermacher that hermeneutics started looking for the foundations of a rigorous methodology to avoid any misinterpretation. Schleiermacher established the principle of the hermeneutic circle: to understand an author (his historical, psychological, environmental context), you need to provide a grammatical analysis of the text (the grammatical features), and&nbsp;to analyze the text you need to understand the author. In other words, this method aims to understand the mind behind the language by explaining how the language is structured in the text. Doing so, this method tries to show that the linguistic context of a text can reflects the historical, sociological, and psychological context (i.e., the contextual features) that influenced its author. </span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Hermeneutics then took a turn in social sciences in the 19<sup>th</sup> century with Wilhelm Dilthey who distinguished the methodology of human sciences and natural sciences: the first, more focused on understanding the psychic life by using intuition, the second explaining the causal relation between facts by analysis. Following this distinction, the 20<sup>th</sup> century saw, with Martin Heidegger and his student Hans-Georg Gadamer, and after them Paul Ric&oelig;ur, the emergence of philosophical hermeneutics which became more explicitly the interpretation of phenomenological, psychic processes, and existential questions, but also textual and symbolic features such as the metaphor.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">It was also during the 20<sup>th</sup> with the help of digital technologies, as shown (J. W. Mohr, R. Wagner, R. Breiger, 2015), that hermeneutics became content analysis procedures consisting of transforming a text into computer-readable digital data sets. These early methods focused on a small, very specific number of units of a text (primary ideas, simple views) to map this textual information into informative units by applying formal methods, regardless of style, nuances of expression, or poetic meaning. On the other hand, humanities pursued a close-reading approach focusing on the complexity of the text (such as its historical context, rhetorical forms, repetitions, syntax, semantics, symbolic mediations, intertextuality, etc.) but coming with a difficult, time-consuming, and always provisional interpretation.&nbsp;</span></span></span></span></span></span><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">With the arrival of Big Data and the presence of new algorithm tools such as AI, the way humans interpret and interact with texts changed drastically. As the authors highlight, the emergence of &ldquo;computational hermeneutics&rdquo; changed not only the methods but also the theoretical approach of the text as a whole, by taking into consideration its relation to a social environment. Notably, these models allow applying formal methods to extract the complexity of the text&#39;s internal structure and meaning in a short amount of time, but also to represent the external features (contextual and cultural) that come with it.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">Particularly, it is with (</span></span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">J. Mallery, R. Hurwitz, G. Duffy, 1986) that we can find one of the first suggestions of reinvesting some principles of traditional hermeneutics for machines&rsquo; text analysis to improve knowledge representation. Inspired by history, the idea of the authors is to reproduce the hermeneutic circle with the help of AI&rsquo;s grammatical analysis. In other words, the idea is that the machine explains the grammatical structure of a text or any kind of proposition to clarify its meaning for humans and makes it possible to infer&nbsp;the contextual components (i.e., psychological, historical, material components) contained in it.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Indeed, for the authors, there is an analogy between the hermeneutic circularity and the computational notion of &ldquo;bootstrapping&rdquo;. As they explain, &ldquo;booting&rdquo; is the process of starting a computer and its software, and involves a loop of steps in which, like a chain reaction, a small program executes a more complex one which then allows another to be launched and which, at the end of the chain reaction, lights up the computer screen. <span style="background:white"><span style="color:#202122">Bootstrapping is in this sense the operation made by the computer to improve itself by interpreting its own programs. As the authors </span></span>observe, <span style="background:white"><span style="color:#202122">the hermeneutics&rsquo; circle shares the same idea of a virtuous circle where the understanding of a text is improved by its grammatical analysis and, reciprocally, its grammatical analysis is made possible by its understanding:</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <blockquote> <p class="MsoQuote" style="margin: 13px 58px 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span style="color:#404040"><span style="font-style:italic"><span lang="EN-US" style="background:white"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="font-style:normal">&ldquo;Hermeneutics theories and applications also share the idea of the hermeneutic circle [&hellip;] Circles or spirals of understanding arise in interpreting one&rsquo;s language [&hellip;] in confirming a theory and in distinguishing between background knowledge and facts. [&hellip;] The grammatical thrust has a bootstrapping flavor: It places the text (or expression) within a particular literature (or language) and reciprocally uses the text to redefine the character of that literature. The psychological thrust more na&iuml;ve and linear. In it, the interpreter reconstructs and explicates the subject&rsquo;s motives and implicit assumptions. Thus, claimed that a successful interpreter could understand the author as well as, or even better than, the author understood himself because the interpretation highlights hidden motives and strategies.&rdquo;</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> </blockquote> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:#202122">This approach of computational hermeneutics models proposes a hermeneutic circle of understanding-explaining transposed to a network of human-computer interaction. The idea is that, in its collaboration with humans, the machine should be able to realize a process of bootstrapping of expanding its understanding of specific fields of science by learning from the data provided by texts written by humans of the domain. The advantage of this approach is that it finds a tempered position between the one of Searle and Turing about AI&rsquo;s understanding ability. Indeed, by distributing and limiting machines to the task of logical and grammatical analysis of texts, computational hermeneutic respects the facts that AIs are nowadays principally technical tools (as Searle defends it), but also, by implying humans in the process of interpretation, it renews Turing&rsquo;s imitation game and allows the machine to learn to interact with them and to reproduce how they use words.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">It is by following this history and idea that our contribution in this perspective article will be to show that the recent state of the art allows us to draw some lines of research for a human-computer interaction based on such a philosophy of language and technology in a pragmatic and hermeneutic approach, i.e., an approach that considers that is from and by practices that AI models can provide efficient content analysis by reproducing a hermeneutic circle with experts.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px">&nbsp;</p> <h2>Problematic and Methodology</h2> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">A hermeneutic project for AI can seem contradictory. How could machines, which are formal systems, be looking for a way to interpret natural language if they only understand formal relations? Indeed, it is only through the inference provided from what they read and the semiotic power of signs that machines can get any information about a world that they don&rsquo;t perceive. In this sense, there is for them a cognitive cloture, i.e., a cognition limit about some facts of the external world that are only accessible through formalism. Therefore,</span></span></span> <span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">the first methodological problem for computational hermeneutics models is to justify how mathematical abstractions could adequately represent phenomena that are, by nature, non-formal. (Bas C. van Fraassen, 2008, p. 240) states the problem in these words:</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <blockquote> <p class="MsoQuote" style="margin: 13px 58px 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span style="color:#404040"><span style="font-style:italic"><span lang="EN" style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="font-style:normal">&ldquo;How can an abstract entity, such as a mathematical structure, represent something that is not abstract, something in nature? </span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="font-style:normal">[&hellip;] We have only access to structures, meaning relations between things. But what is exactly the relation between the empirical data and the mathematical formalism of the theory?&rdquo;</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> </blockquote> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Reformulated in our context, how could data correspond to empirical facts such as the propositional content of a text? And how the grammatical structure of a proposition could represent the context from where it emerges?</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">From this problem of correspondence between empirical data and abstract structures, there is also a problem of application of these structures. As (F. Rastier, 2004) highlights, there is no perfect natural language translation by formal languages, which makes it impossible to provide a unique and objective model able to analyze every kind of language or text. Every linguistic item (words, terms, expressions, grammatical relations) has a specific nature and the degree of complexity of its relation with others is always dependent on a specific context of use. In other words, languages and texts cannot be analyzed or represented by the same formal relations, otherwise, it would lead to projecting a &ldquo;structured prejudice&rdquo; to every kind of language or text without respect to their differences (of genres, uses, meaning).</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">To answer these two problems, we are going to see that computational hermeneutics models can manage the relation between empirical data and their formal representation by building the models directly in and by the practices, avoiding at the same time any preconceived structure. In other words, these models are specifically built by and through the context of sociolinguistics domains of practices and, therefore, propose an approach to manage the variability of meaning between linguistic practices and respect their differences without trying to unify them in one&nbsp;language or objective structure.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">First, we are going to present the ontological foundation for a pragmatic approach. We will see how C. S. Peirce&rsquo;s semiotics theory can express situations and practices in the world, and how this approach can be implemented in the AI context through John Sowa&rsquo;s conceptual graphs. Based on this theoretical background, we will show that meaning between humans and machines is co-constructed directly in their interactions through signs.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">In a second time, we are going to present computer ontologies, AIs that can be used to apply computational hermeneutics models. We will see that these knowledge organization systems share common properties with the philosophy behind hermeneutics, especially about the language-world relation, and can be considered&nbsp;as tools used to provide semantic interoperability between systems and agents.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Then we will present some applications of computational hermeneutics models that combine both principles and tools we will have defined. We will see that by providing formal and semantics graphs of knowledge and statistics on the recurrences of words in a text or any kind of sociolinguistic domain these models will be able to build and represent precise definitions of how humans use some words according to some context. Also, by reasoning on these data, machines should be able to learn from a database directly built from and in the practices, leading to clear and logical inferences about the concepts that constitute their domain. </span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">This will lead us, in conclusion, to propose to try to define what it means &ldquo;to mean&rdquo; for machines and humans according to these analyses.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; text-indent:35.4pt; margin-bottom:11px">&nbsp;</p> <h2>Semiotics as Ontological Foundation</h2> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">For an ontological foundation of the computational hermeneutics models that work with a pragmatic program, we can rely on (J. Sowa, 2000, 2008, 2013, 2015) who developed an approach in AI taking care of the relations between language and the world by applying the logical theory of signs of C. S. Peirce</span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">. The field of semiotics itself owes a large part of this codification to (C. S. Peirce, 1994, p. 362):&nbsp;</span></span></span></span></span></span><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">&ldquo;(CP 2.227) Logic has no other general name than semiotics, the formal doctrine of signs. [&hellip;] By formal, I mean that we observe the characters of the signs and that we only know this observation, by a process that I will have no objection to calling abstraction [&hellip;].&rdquo;</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">If the purpose of hermeneutics is to seek the meaning of signs in a text, semiotics is here the study of the rules and laws of their manipulation in a logical structure. Also (J. Sowa, 2000) noticed that, for Peirce, <span style="background:white"><span style="color:black">semiotics is the science that studies the use of signs by &ldquo;any scientific intelligence&rdquo;. J. Sowa considers that Peirce means here &ldquo;any intelligence capable of learning by experience&rdquo;, including animal intelligence and even mindlike processes in an inanimate matter such as computers. In this sense (J. Sowa, 2015) shows that computer techniques for AI to manage knowledge bases could meet Peirce&rsquo;s criteria about apprehending signs and his theory could be used as a semiotic foundation for ontology.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family: &quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif; font-size: 12pt; text-indent: 35.4pt;"><span style="line-height:150%">And it is indeed true that semiotics and logical thinking are connected for Peirce and not limited to linguistic perspectives. For Peirce, a sign can be an object, a thought, or a judgment, and there are different types of signs that he categorized according to their logical function. Perceiving a sign is obtained by what he calls an &ldquo;abstractive observation&rdquo; which Peirce describes as an experience of perception of the thing in the mind. He describes this experiment as akin to mathematical reasoning: the experience of abstractive observation consists of creating a &ldquo;skeleton diagram&rdquo; or a &ldquo;silhouette diagram&rdquo; of a proposition to represent its structures and logical laws with clarity. </span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family: &quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif; font-size: 12pt; text-indent: 35.4pt;"><span style="line-height:150%">By renewing the triadic relation thought-symbol-world of Aristotle, (C. S. Peirce, 1994, p. 363) proposed a semiotic triangle interpretant-representamen-object to define the structure a sign takes&nbsp;to mean something:</span></span></p> <blockquote> <p class="MsoQuote" style="margin: 13px 58px 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span style="color:#404040"><span style="font-style:italic"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="font-style:normal">&ldquo;(CP 2.228) A sign, or representamen, is something which stands to somebody for something in some respect or capacity. It addresses somebody, that is, creates in the mind of that person an equivalent sign, or perhaps a more developed sign. That sign which it creates I call the interpretant of the first sign. The sign stands for something, its object. It stands for that object, not in all respects, but in reference to a sort of idea, which I have sometimes called the ground of the representamen.&rdquo;</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> </blockquote> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">The sign is defined by a triadic relationship between i) the representamen, ii) an object, and iii) the<b> </b>interpretant.<b> </b>The representamen is the form that the sign takes, &ldquo;something that stands for someone in some respect or title&rdquo;: the name &ldquo;Ulysses&rdquo; for example is the representamen of a cat called Ulysses; the object (a cat) is what is represented; and the interpretant is a judgment or a representation of an object by a subject applied to the object thanks to its representamen. Here, the semiosis, the process of meaning that constitutes the sign, is involved in this triadic relation: the interpretant becomes a concept or a thought of &ldquo;cat&rdquo; thanks to the representamen &ldquo;Ulysses&rdquo; which stands for the physical object &ldquo;cat&rdquo;.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">The interest of such a conception of signs is that Peirce takes into consideration the semiosis as a process of perception and logical thinking according to practical effects: a sign does not have the same meaning as another sign depending on the context it is perceived and used. Based on such principles, Peirce manages to develop &ldquo;existential graphs&rdquo; which put in correspondence signs, logical inferences, and knowledge representation of concepts. The interest of these graphs is that </span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">dispose of equivalence with symbolic languages allowing us to express some concepts analytically and also by a graphical representation.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">It is by following this idea of maintaining the clarity of knowledge by graphical representation like the existential graphs and signs that (J. Sowa, 2008) developed for informatics his own &ldquo;conceptual graphs&rdquo; which aim to unify the computational linguistics, the logic based on the semantic networks, and the cognitive support of machine reasoning processes. These conceptual graphs reproduce Peirce&rsquo;s existential graphs in that they can also be translated into logical propositions. They have multiple topological forms (hierarchical, cyclic, lists, etc.) or logical relations and allow representing graphically on a computer screen the syntactic structure of the elements composing a proposition in the natural language like: &ldquo;John takes the bus to go to Boston&rdquo; which expresses a fact in the world.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">For example, in this proposition, knowledge can be represented in a formal structure that is made up of concepts, themselves divided into a semantic network of categories: agent, object, action, places, and else. In the graph, each of the four main [concepts] represents the type of entity to which it refers: [John], [Go], [Boston], or [Bus]. One of them expresses the main action, [Go], that centralized the graph, and the three others have names that identify their referent: &ldquo;John&rdquo;, &ldquo;Boston&rdquo;, and &ldquo;Bus&rdquo;. Also, these concepts are linked to a label in parentheses which represents the (class) to which they belong: agent (Agnt), destination (Dest), person (Person), or instrument (Inst). Then, the graph describes knowledge as follows by connecting concepts and classes together: [John] is an (Agnt) and an instance of the class of (Person), [Boston] is an instance of the class (city) and is a (Dest), and the [Bus] is an (Inst) to [Go] to [Boston]. For (J. Sowa, 2008), this graph can also be translated by the following formula which thus becomes a resource that can also be readable by a machine by paraphrasing it with logical signs: </span></span><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">&exist;</span></span><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">x</span></span><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">&exist;</span></span><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">y (Go(x) </span></span><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">&and;</span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black"> Person(John) </span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">&and;</span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black"> City(Boston) </span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">&and;</span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black"> Bus(y) </span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">&and;</span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black"> Agnt(x, John) </span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">&and;</span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black"> Dest(x, Boston) </span></span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">&and;</span></span><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black"> Inst(x, y)).</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Here, the interest of such conceptual graphs for computational hermeneutics models is that their form <span style="color:black">expresses the logical relation between signs, making them readable by both humans and machines. </span></span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">As (J. Sowa, 2013) summarized it:</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <blockquote> <p class="MsoQuote" style="margin: 13px 58px 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span style="color:#404040"><span style="font-style:italic"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black"><span style="font-style:normal">&nbsp;&ldquo;Graphs have advantages over linear notations in human factors, computational efficiency, and cognitive representation. For readability, graphs show relationships at a glance that are harder to see in linear notations. They also have a highly regular structure that can simplify many algorithms for reasoning, searching, indexing, and pattern matching&rdquo;.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> </blockquote> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Thus, the application of conceptual graphs makes knowledge intelligible and interpretable for both humans and machines:</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <ul> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Materially: Taken as such, the sign is the material mark that stands for the entities it represents in the proposition. (e.g., the letters x, y, z as variables).</span></span></span></span></span></span></li> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Relationally: The sign puts one thing in a specific relation with another. (e.g., the relation &ldquo;Dest(x, y)&rdquo; where an object x go to a destination y).</span></span></span></span></span></span></li> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Formally: The sign makes it possible to organize the syntactic entities together to formulate a proposition that can attribute properties to an object. (e.g. &ldquo;</span><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif">&exist;</span><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">xPx&rdquo; where P is any predicate of an object x).</span></span></span></span></span></span></li> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Contextually: The sign refers to a situation and tries to put in concepts contextual knowledge of propositions (e.g., the fact in the world that John takes the bus to go to Boston). The definition of the sign then also takes place under the context in which it is applied.</span></span></span></span></span></span></li> </ul> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">This pragmatic approach of interpreting signs can serve as an ontological foundation&nbsp;for the use of computer ontologies, according to the fact that these AIs models are specifically designed in and by an interaction with linguistics practices to produce formal and semantic knowledge graphs. Indeed, computer ontologies can be built on texts and contexts of scientific fields through collaborative practices among experts in different fields of science. Now, we do not intend to present the technical details of how automated reasoning for higher-order logic can aim at formalizing natural-language argumentative discourse (for this, see (D. Fuenmayor, C. Benzm&uuml;ller, 2019)), but rather we will present how, through the general hermeneutics principles and their application to computer ontologies, we can see a logical analysis and a conceptual explanation of the entities contained in the propositions of a text can be provided.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px">&nbsp;</p> <h2>Knowledge Reasoning and Representation With Computer Ontologies</h2> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Computer ontologies are related to philosophical Ontology in that they aim to structure the entities (e.g., concepts, objects) contained in a domain of specialty by specifying their logical and linguistic relationships&nbsp;to contextualize this domain, but also the level of concretization or abstraction. </span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">They are AI models that seem the most suitable for our purpose, because, as <span style="color:black">(F. Neuhaus, 2023) </span>explains, &ldquo;they can provide standardized and controlled vocabulary [&hellip;], specify their vocabulary semantic in both machine and human-readable form [&hellip;], they may also represent empirical knowledge&rdquo;. These models are therefore more explainable and transparent than large language models (LLMs) and manage interoperability between agents (humans and machines) by resolving ambiguities where LLMs often &ldquo;navigate through them&rdquo; if used alone.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">In these models, machines learn from data the contextual uses and meaning of words and, reciprocally, help humans to understand with more clarity the logical layout of scientific knowledge. (R. Davis, H. Shrobe, P. Szolovits, 1993) <span style="background:white"><span style="color:#222222">categorized this relation external world/internal system for knowledge representation as follows </span></span>in KR&sup2;</span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">:</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <blockquote> <p class="MsoQuote" style="margin: 13px 58px 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span style="color:#404040"><span style="font-style:italic"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="font-style:normal">&ldquo;Any intelligent entity that wishes to reason about its world encounters an important, inescapable fact: reasoning is a process that goes on internally, while most things it wishes to reason about exist only externally. A program (or person) engaged in planning the assembly of a bicycle, for instance, may have to reason about entities like wheels, chains, sprockets, handle bars, etc., yet such things exist only in the external world. This unavoidable dichotomy is a fundamental rationale and role for a representation: it functions as a surrogate inside the reasoner, a stand-in for the things that exist in the world. Operations on and with representations substitute for operations on the real thing, i.e., substitute for direct interaction with the world. In this view reasoning itself is in part a surrogate for action in the world, when we cannot or do not (yet) want to take that action.&rdquo;</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> </blockquote> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Inevitably, there is a dichotomy between the formal internal system of a machine and the external fact of the world. As we saw it, the machine has only access to the computer representation of empirical facts. Then, the purpose of representing knowledge in a computer can be understood as finding a correspondence between the external world and the symbolic formal system it uses for reasoning.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">This dialectic shows us the proximity between KR&sup2; and hermeneutics in their purpose: hermeneutics tries to understand the external and contextual features that influence the internal intention and inner thought of an author by analyzing the grammatical structures of a text, and KR&sup2; tries to implement the external facts of the world in an internal formal system called &ldquo;Knowledge Organization System (KOS)&rdquo; (e.g., digital libraries, taxonomies, dictionaries, lists, computer ontologies)</span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">. Therefore, both share this duality external/internal and aim to find a path of linking them through&nbsp;an analysis of language.</span></span></span> <span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">(G. Hodge, 2000) presents in three main points how this relation between external facts and the internal system can be organized into a computer system:</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <ul> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">A KOS imposes a particular view of the world on a collection and the items in it. </span></span></span></span></span></span></li> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">The same entity can be characterized in different ways, depending on the KOS that is used. </span></span></span></span></span></span></li> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">There must be enough in common between the concept expressed in a KOS and the real-world object to which that concept refers that a knowledgeable person could apply the system with reasonable reliability. Likewise, a person seeking relevant material by using a KOS must be able to connect his or her concept with its representation in the system.</span></span></span></span></span></span></li> </ul> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">KR&sup2; is therefore a field that uses formal systems to represent and manipulate general knowledge by formalizing concepts into informatics models. In KR&sup2;, machines like computer ontologies can be used to semantically represent knowledge.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">For computer ontologies, the relations between concepts can be manipulated and interpreted&nbsp;to fix a specific context of science. </span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">In the KR&sup2;&rsquo;s context, </span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">a computer ontology can be presented as a computer artifact that formally represents in a lattice the common knowledge or the language practice of a field of specialties from a semantic point of view. As (S. Staab, R. Studer, 2004) explain, &ldquo;</span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Ontology is the study of &ldquo;things that exist&rdquo;, within the domain of computer science an ontology is a formal model that allows reasoning about concepts and objects that appear in the real world and (crucially) about the complex relationship between them&rdquo;. T</span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">heir knowledge base can be made up of a corpus of texts on which it can be applied techniques of hypertext and semantic graphs&nbsp;to structure their data and reflect the &ldquo;relationship between objects in the real world&rdquo; by using languages allowing description. For example, one of them, OWL (Web Ontology Language), allows the machine to specify the relation of subsumption (&ldquo;x is_a y&rdquo;) between entities, classes, or concepts.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">The computer ontology is presented in a diagram like a mind map or a semantic network. This form allows contextualizing the relationships that entities of a given domain have with each other. <span style="color:black">Several types of ontologies (top ontologies, core ontologies, and domain ontologies) can be used separately or in combination with the same or separate domains to specify different kinds of entities and levels of abstraction (for example, metaphysical concepts with top ontologies, interdisciplinary concepts with core ontologies, and concrete and domain-related concepts by domain ontologies).</span></span></span></span> <span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">To build them (T. Gruber, 1994) defines epistemological precepts such as clarity (i.e., avoiding ambiguities), coherence (i.e., avoiding inferences or axioms that imply&nbsp;contradictions), extendibility (i.e., being able to deal with polysemy), minimal encoding bias (i.e., minimizing the dependence of knowledge of a particular formalism) and minimal ontological commitment (i.e., maintaining a correspondence vocabularies and entities and concepts of a domain) that aims to ensure their correspondence with their external environment and interoperability with other systems and agents.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">In other words, ontologies are interesting tools for our purpose </span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">because they need but also provide interdisciplinary exchanges between philosophers, AIs, linguists, and experts of a domain to formalize texts and languages in the service of knowledge engineering. Combining their roles in the development of terminologies and the corpus of ontologies, this interdisciplinarity centralized by AI makes possible the learning loop necessary for computational hermeneutic models, thus allowing them to represent with multiple perspectives the different degrees of generalization of the entities that constitute texts and their fields of application.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">However, the representative function of these AIs does not provide any realism or reveal&nbsp;the objective conceptual structures of the agents&rsquo; minds who use them. These systems only help to make intelligible a cultural and social background and help experts&nbsp;understand it and make&nbsp;inferences about the meaning of structured data.</span></span></span> <span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Therefore, we defend here the same instrumental position of (G. Declerck, J. Charlet, 2014), considering that ontologies are principally tools used to enhance human cognitive abilities and play the role of mediator between agents. </span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Now we have defined the principles and the tools we are using we can present some applications of computational hermeneutics models.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; text-indent:35.4pt; margin-bottom:11px">&nbsp;</p> <h2>Computational Hermeneutic Models as Collaborative Systems</h2> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">As (J. Mallery, R. Hurwitz, G. Duffy, 1986) put it, these models try to pursue the art of traditional hermeneutics with the help of continual feedback between its internal (grammatical) and external (author&rsquo;s context) features. In other words, computational hermeneutics models aim to apply the traditional hermeneutic circle of understanding-explaining to a network of human-computer interaction where text analysis serves as a basis to help both improve their understanding of a sociolinguistic context. </span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Here, the text is a cultural artifact used to feed a machine with data, and their </span></span></span><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">logical analysis of contextual and intentional features aims to provide experts with a clear overview of their domain. Computational hermeneutics models should be able to accomplish several tasks that can be combined:</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <ul> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:#202122">Contextualize meaning: The model should be trained into a hermeneutic network allowing the machine to be trained in a sociolinguistic environment, providing it with several acceptations of the meaning of a word according to the practices of its users (meeting here (L., Wittgenstein, 1958, &sect;43)&rsquo;principle according to which &ldquo;the meaning of a word is its use in language&rdquo;).</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></li> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:#202122">Genre classification: The model should be able to classify the entities of a text or a domain to state the type of corpuses and categorize their features, such as the emotion the text expresses (e.g., romantic novel, political discourses, thriller, informatics codes), or the terms and concepts a domain is accepting (e.g., classes, individuals, instances, properties).</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></li> <li style="text-align: justify; margin-bottom: 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:#202122">Semantic mapping: The model should be able to learn and represent the grammatical and formal relations and features of the entities by mapping them dynamically into semantic networks or conceptual graphs, just like children are learning the meaning of words from a graphical representation. By this mapping, the machine can formalize the relations of the objects and propositions of a domain or contained in a text and represent them in a comprehensible way for humans.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></li> </ul> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">To contextualize meaning, this conception of hermeneutics in AI can lead to a &ldquo;hermeneutic network&rdquo; proposed by (J. Zhu, D. F. Harrell, 2009) which aims to analyze the narration of a text through the&nbsp;interaction of authors and&nbsp;machines. The purpose here is to help the machine to acquire an &ldquo;intentional vocabulary&rdquo;, i.e., a lexicon of words that the humans define according to their understanding of their meaning. For the same word different users could have a different understanding:&nbsp;then each of them has to inscribe the&nbsp;definition they have in the machine to allow it to enrich its internal vocabulary. The idea is that the more the machine manages this &ldquo;flexibility of meanings&rdquo;, i.e., the several understandings a word can have, the more it will be able to manage eventual ambiguities and in which context and purposes a word may be used.</span></span></span></span></span><i> </i><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">In the hermeneutic network, users write their own social experiences and cultural backgrounds into the computer system when they interact with the machine to convey to it the meaning of the words they use</span></span></span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">. In other words, the hermeneutic network reproduces Wittgenstein&rsquo;s concept of &ldquo;community of language&rdquo; according to which meaning is collectivity and dynamically built by shared practices.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">To classify the genre of a text and its narrative structure (H. R. Alker, W. G. Lehneret, D. K. Schneider, 1985) propose a model to extract its affective contents by working on contextual units (such as the relationships between the characters, the events they are facing, or the affects they express) and aim to summarize their story by representing their relations. By analyzing the context and the connections between these narrative elements, the affective core of the text can be compared to some others, allowing the machine to state its genre. For example, the authors concluded that the events of Jesus&rsquo;s story conform to a well-known genre which was the romance of self-transcendence.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">On the same idea, the intentional content of a text can be exposed by an analysis of its structure, here, based on the recurrences and uses of words. (D. Mayaffre, 2002) provides the analysis of a discourse of French politics in 1930 from the right-wing based on the occurrence of the verb &ldquo;having&rdquo;, declined in &ldquo;to have&rdquo; and &ldquo;has&rdquo;. This</span></span></span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black"> right-wing discourse shows a passive observation of the social situation in the 1930s where the word &ldquo;have&rdquo; is most often conjugated to the past, when by comparison some discourses of the left-wing in the same era are rather conjugated to the future. (D. Mayaffre, 2002) observes that this speech evokes conservatism and that this affective feature seems to be inscribed in the grammatical structure of the speech given its temporal form, and he infers that this affective trait (conservatism) would be in the mind of the speaker or in what it aimed to mean or to transmit to its auditorium.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">For semantic mapping (J. C. Mallery, G. Duffy, 1986) propose a model of &ldquo;semantic perception&rdquo; that allows the machine to realize a semantic analysis of data from syntactic forms. </span></span></span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">Formally, semantic mapping takes its inspiration from the semantic memory of (R. Quillian, A. Collins, 1968) which aimed to produce a structural model representing the cognitive activity of the association of ideas in the mind. Here each node represents concepts or ideas and every arc is the connection between them. <span style="background:white">By formalizing lexical items into different classes of words, this model takes into consideration the polysemy and intentional structure of communicative situations. It aims to represent the grammatical relations that words could manage together and, by a process of mapping, the model formalized words into relations that a machine could handle. The graph can also be used to represent the association of ideas and their relations that a domain of knowledge maintains, just as the conceptual graphs.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">All of these models aim to provide a model of a domain of discourse through a formalization of its uses by the means of an exchange between humans and machines. As (D. Fuenmayor, C. Benzm&uuml;ller, 2019) put it, experts are involved in a &ldquo;dialectical exchange with the computer&rdquo; in which it extends its database from the axioms inscribed by the experts, and by the inferences and graph representation that it provides in return, it allows experts to clarify logical relations between entities.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Also, we can see that these models respond to Moravec&rsquo;s paradox that states that what is easy for the human is difficult for the machine (e.g., understanding contextual meaning), and what is easy for the machine is difficult for the human (e.g., making complex computations). Here, the explanatory power of machines is used in tandem with the natural understanding of humans to answer any question about meaning. Therefore, we can attempt to define the philosophy of these models in these terms:</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Def.:<i><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"> </span></span></span></i>A computational hermeneutics model is a collaborative system between humans and machines for textual data analysis. To understand the contextual meaning of words machines need humans, and to explain the logical and grammatical structure humans need machines. In this circle, both are improved in their capacity to understand and explain the meaning of the text and the contextual features of the propositions of a language. The objectivity of the model is then provided by the interaction it implies between agents.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px">&nbsp;</p> <h2>Conclusion: What Does It Mean &ldquo;to Mean&rdquo; for The Machine?</h2> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">We have presented in this article some possibilities for computational hermeneutics models, their purpose, and principles by reproducing Schleiermacher&rsquo;s hermeneutic circle in&nbsp;a digital context. We have investigated the feasibility of hermeneutics in AI through the principles of Peirce&rsquo;s semiotics and pragmatics applied to conceptual graphs with (J. Sowa, 2000, 2008, 2013, 2015)&rsquo;s models, and we also saw, following Wittgenstein, how the uses of words can be defining their meaning in a hermeneutic network (<span style="background:white"><span style="color:black">J. Zhu, D. F. Harrell, 2009). By using ontologies (Fuenmayor D., Benzm&uuml;ller C., 2019) and logometric analyses (D. Mayaffre, 2002) to provide semantic representations (J. C. Mallery, G. Duffy, 1986) or gender classifications (H. R. Alker, W. G. Lehneret, D. K. Schneider, 1985), we have seen how AI can support the cognitive activity of interpretation of humans by analyzing the uses of words, by building dictionaries applicable to specific or different contexts, or by avoiding projecting a genre pre-structured on a text by making it emerge directly from its composition.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">However, if we want a hermeneutic network between humans and machines to be effective, that is to say, able to serve as a circuit in which the meaning of texts is understandable between the participants, we must also adopt the point of view of the machines and ask in which sense they &ldquo;mean&rdquo; something. </span></span></span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">The problem is that these models do not use, learn, and understand the meaning of words, practices, and texts as humans do. They are essentially mathematical tools and not intentional beings, and this distinction suggests redefining the question of meaning in the context of digital hermeneutics, which is what we attempt to do now.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">To be able to mean something seems, at first sight, to be able to use a language to intentionally signify something (an idea, a proposition, an emotion, or else). However, machines do not &ldquo;use&rdquo; language to mean things just as humans do. What they do is only computing and the way they express something is by automatically and mechanically responding to requests or accomplishing tasks. Also, a machine does not have biological organs nor can perceive things directly: it only recognizes and represents things through formal structures. In other words, the only thing that &ldquo;exists&rdquo; for AI systems is, as (T. Gruber, 1993) noticed, &ldquo;what can be represented&rdquo;, i.e., what is formally inscribed in its internal system. This position implies, as (B. Bachimont, 2022) notes, that there are no &ldquo;words&rdquo; or &ldquo;propositions&rdquo; or even such a thing called &ldquo;text&rdquo; for a machine because a text is an object whose content always refers to an external, existential, and meaningful ecosystem where humans are living. We can&rsquo;t even properly say that machines &ldquo;read&rdquo; anything, or only if by &ldquo;reading&rdquo; we assume that what computers only do is &ldquo;computing numerical signs&rdquo;.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Thus, it seems imprecise to use the verb &ldquo;to mean&rdquo; for AI, because it implicitly implies an intentional feature. However, if we agree on the fact that machines do not&nbsp;&ldquo;signify&rdquo; things, we can state that they &ldquo;express&rdquo; results that can have meaning for humans. Therefore, we suggest that the question &ldquo;What does it mean &ldquo;to mean&rdquo;?&rdquo; when it comes to machines in the context of computational hermeneutics models should be replaced by the question &ldquo;What does it mean to express something?&rdquo;, which is easier to answer because it is more specified and put aside the intentional implicit of the verb &ldquo;to mean&rdquo;. We can also clarify the problem more accurately by following the formulation of (C. Taylor, 1985, p. 219) about meaning and how it is expressed:</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <blockquote> <p class="MsoQuote" style="margin: 13px 58px 11px;"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span style="color:#404040"><span style="font-style:italic"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="font-style:normal">&ldquo;What is meant by &#39;expression&#39; here? I think it means roughly this: something is expressed when it is embodied in such a way as to be made manifest. And &#39;manifest&#39; must be taken here in a strong sense. Something is manifest when it is directly available for all to see. It is not manifest when there are just signs of its presence, from which we can infer that it is there, such as when I &#39;see&#39; that you are in your office because of your car being parked outside. [&nbsp;&hellip;] Expression makes something manifest in embodying it.&rdquo;</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> </blockquote> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">Here, Taylor emphasizes the fact that language isn&rsquo;t just a mechanical function but also produces a range of symbolic forms, i.e., structures of meaning that need to be embedded in a medium to be interpreted. The relation between meaning and its expression is organic: it can only be expressed when it is embodied and structured to be manifest.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">We can transpose this definition into our context by considering that meaning circulates in the hermeneutic network when humans inscribe data into the machines&rsquo; system that they structure into a symbolic form. That is to say that &ldquo;to mean&rdquo; for an AI in the context of computational hermeneutics models is providing a symbolic form or formal bodie<i>s</i> (e.g., semantic networks, conceptual graphs, computer ontologies) of the data inscribed in its system to make it clear for experts.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">These symbolic forms are not only pure abstract structures but inscriptions that carry with them the environment from which they come. It would be an &ldquo;inscription error&rdquo;, as <span style="color:black">(B. C. Smith, 1998) </span>calls them, to think that the data provided by computers are not influenced by the dynamic in which they are built and produced. We also join here <span style="color:black">(J. Cavaill&egrave;s, 1997) when he </span>explains that any presence of mathematical symbols necessarily implies manipulations. Mathematical signs (numbers, figures, even sticks) certainly do not refer to an external world, but they are correlated to the actions that use and inscribe them. Therefore, no formalism can claim to be absolutely separate from sensibility or culture and if&nbsp;the &ldquo;theory of science can be clarified and specified by formalization, it is not constituted by them.&rdquo; (J. Cavaill&egrave;s, 1997, p. 53, our translation).</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Now we can respond to the problem of correspondence of van Fraassenn, by considering that mathematical structures are not only abstract entities because they are produced from a context of practices, and machines provide data that can&rsquo;t be not derived from an ecosystem. <span style="color:black">T<span style="background:white">herefore, from a pragmatist point of view, the dichotomy between the external world and the internal system of the machine vanishes. To</span></span> respond to the symbol grounding problem, if it is not possible to inscribe meaning directly into the data it is because it is already in it, but it is only with the conjoin forces of humans and machines that we can make it manifest.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">In other words, if AIs are not intelligent, conscious, or organic entities capable of perceiving the world, their computational activity is not meaningless nonetheless. By entering data from a domain into their systems, AI necessarily improves their analytics capacities by learning from it. And, by structuring these data, they provide symbolic forms that experts interpret and can restructure to feed again the machine to bring out refined data. This learning loop between humans and machines causes new knowledge to emerge precisely from the human-machine interaction and this process can be reproduced until reaching a fixed point. <span style="color:black">From a pragmatic point of view, the hermeneutic network can then be considered as an activity of documentation and re-documentation about itself, trying to understand its own linguistic and epistemological ambiguities, cultural and methodological biases, i.e., a meta-hermeneutic process.</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="margin-bottom:11px">&nbsp;</p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><b><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Acknowledgment </span></span></span></b></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:150%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">We warmly thank Adrien Barton and Jean Charlet for their proofreading, comments, and helpful feedback.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px">&nbsp;</p> <h2>Bibliography</h2> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Alker Jr. H.R., Lehnert W.G., Schneider D. K. (1985). Two Reinterpretations of Tonbee&rsquo;s Jesus: Explorations in Computational Hermeneutics. In <i>G. Tonfoni, ed. Artificial Intelligence and Text Understanding. Quaderni di Ricerca Linguistica</i>, 6, 49-94</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Bachimont B. (2022). La complexit&eacute; herm&eacute;neutique &agrave; l&rsquo;&eacute;preuve du calcul. <i>Interfaces num&eacute;riques</i>, 10(3), </span></span></span><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif">&lang;</span></span></span><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">10.25965/interfaces-numeriques.4686</span></span></span><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif">&rang;</span></span></span><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">.&nbsp;</span></span></span><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif">&lang;</span></span></span><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">hal-03906427</span></span></span><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Cambria Math&quot;,serif">&rang;</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Cavaill&egrave;s J. (1997). <i>Sur la logique et la th&eacute;orie de la science</i>, Vrin</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Declerck G., Charlet J. (2014). Pourquoi notre s&eacute;mantique na&iuml;ve n&rsquo;est pas formalisable et pourquoi c&rsquo;est (presque) sans cons&eacute;quence sur l&rsquo;ing&eacute;nierie ontologique. In: <i>Intellectica. Revue de l&#39;Association pour la Recherche Cognitive</i>, n&deg;61, Philosophie du Web et Ing&eacute;nierie des Connaissances. pp. 143-188</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Fraassen (van) Bas C. (2008). <i>Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective</i>. Oxford University Press, Clarendon Press</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoFootnoteText" style="border:none; text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="color:black"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Fuenmayor D., Benzm&uuml;ller C. (2019). A Computational-Hermeneutic Approach for Conceptual Explicitation. arXiv:1906.06582v2 [cs.AI]</span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:#131314">Gruber T., (1994). Toward Principles for the Design of Ontologies Used for Knowledge Sharing. <i>International Journal of Human-Computer Studies</i>, 43(5-6)</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Harnad S., (1990). The Symbol Grounding Problem. <i>Physica D: Nonlinear Phenomena, Elsevier</i>, Volume 42, Issues 1-3, June 1990, Pages 335-346</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoFootnoteText" style="border:none; text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="color:black"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Hodge G., (2000). <i>Systems of Knowledge Organization for Digital Libraries: Beyond Traditional Authority Files</i>. </span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">The Digital Library Federation Council on Library and Information Resources 1755 Massachusetts Avenue, NW, Suite 500 Washington, DC 20036</span></span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoFootnoteText" style="border:none; text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="color:black"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Mallery J., Hurwitz R., Duffy G. (1986). Hermeneutics: From Textual Explication to Computer Understanding. Massachusetts Institute of Technology, <i>Artificial Intelligence Laboratory, A.I. Memo No. 871</i></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Mallery J. C., Duffy G. (1986). A Computational Model of Semantic Perception. </span></span></span><i><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">AI Memo No. 799, Artificial Intelligence Laboratory</span></span></span></i><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">, MIT, Cambridge</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Mayaffre D. (2002). L&rsquo;Herm&eacute;neutique num&eacute;rique. <i>L&rsquo;Astrolabe, Recherche litt&eacute;raire et Informatique</i>, 2002, pp.1-11. hal-00586512</span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Mohr J. W., Wagner R., Breiger R. (2015). Toward a computational hermeneutics. <i>Big Data &amp; Society</i>, 2(2)</span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:#131314">Neuhaus F. (2023). Ontologies in the era of large language models &ndash; a perspective. <i>Applied Ontology</i>, 18(4):399-407</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoFootnoteText" style="border:none; text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="color:black"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Peirce C. S. (1994). <i>Collected Papers of C. S. Peirce</i> (CP). electronic edition reproducing Vols. I-VI ed. Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1931-1935), Vols. VII-VIII, ed. Arthur W. Burks (same publisher, 1958)</span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Quillian M. R., Collins A. M. (1968). Retrieval Time from Semantic Memory. Bolt Beranek and Newman, Inc., Cambridge, Massachusetts, <i>Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior</i>, 8, 240-247</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:#333333">Rastier F. (2004). Ontologie(s). C.N.R.S.</span></span></span></span><span style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">,&nbsp;<i>Revue des sciences et technologies de l&rsquo;information, s&eacute;rie&nbsp;:&nbsp;Revue d&rsquo;Intelligence artificielle</i>, vol. 18, n&deg;1, p. 15-4</span></span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoNoSpacing" style="text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Searle J. R. (1980). Minds, Brains and Programs. <i>The Behavorial and Brain Sciences, </i>Vol. 3, Cambridge University Press</span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoNoSpacing" style="text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Smith C. B. (1998). <i>On the Origins of Objects</i>, The MIT Press</span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoNoSpacing" style="text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Sowa J. (2000). <i>Ontology, Metadata, and Semiotics</i>. <span style="background:white"><span style="color:black">ICCS&#39;2000 in Darmstadt, Germany, Published in B. Ganter &amp; G. W. Mineau, eds.,&nbsp;Conceptual Structures: Logical, Linguistics, and Computational Issues, Lecture Notes in AI #1867, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, pp. 55-81.</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoNoSpacing" style="text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Sowa J. (2008). <i>Conceptual Graphs</i>. </span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">preprint of Chapter 5 of the Handbook of Knowledge Representation, ed. by F. van Harmelen, V. Lifschitz, and B. Porter, Elsevier, pp. 213-237</span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoNoSpacing" style="text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Sowa J. (2013). From Existential Graphs to Conceptual Graphs. <i>International Journal of Conceptual Structures and Smart Applications</i>, 1(1):39-72</span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoNoSpacing" style="text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="background:white"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif"><span style="color:black">Sowa J. (2015). </span></span></span></span><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Signs and reality. <i>Applied ontology</i>, <span style="background:white"><span style="color:#333333">10 (3-4):273-284</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoNoSpacing" style="text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Staab S., Studer R. (2004). <i>Handbook on Ontologies. International Handbooks on Information Systems</i>, Springer</span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Taylor C. (1985). <i>Human Agency and Language</i>. McGill University, Montr&eacute;al, Cambridge University Press </span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing Machinery and Intelligence. <i>Mind</i>, Vol. 59, No. 236 (Oct., 1950), pp. 433-460</span></span></span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoNoSpacing" style="text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:11pt"><span style="font-family:Calibri, sans-serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Uschold M., Grunninger M. (1996). Ontologies: Principles, Methods and Applications. <i>Knowledge Engineering Review</i>, vol.11, n&deg;2</span></span></span></span></p> <p class="MsoFootnoteText" style="border:none; text-align:justify"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="color:black"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Wittgenstein L. (1958). <i>Philosophical Investigations</i>. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe, Blackwell</span></span></span></span></span></p> <p style="text-align:justify; margin-bottom:11px"><span style="font-size:12pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;, serif"><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">Zhu J., Harrell D. F. (2009). </span></span></span><i><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">System Intentionality and the Artificial Intelligence Hermeneutic Network: The Role of Intentional Vocabulary</span></span></span></i><span lang="EN-US" style="font-size:12.0pt"><span style="line-height:106%"><span style="font-family:&quot;Times New Roman&quot;,serif">. UC Irvine, California Digital Library, University of California</span></span></span></span></span></span></p>